Making Sense of the Marriage Debate

Jane S. Schacter

91 Texas L. Rev. 1185

PDF Document

Schacter reviews Michael J. Klarman’s From the Closet to the Altar: Courts, Backlash, and the Struggle for Same-Sex Marriage.

Jury Unanimity and the Problem with Specificity: Trying to Understand What Jurors Must Agree About by Examining the Problem of Prosecuting Child Molesters

Brian Bah

91 Texas L. Rev. 1203

PDF Document

In this Note, Mr. Bah argues that one way to approach questions about the level of specificity required for jury agreement is by examining current state laws and their various jury agreement doctrines.  Continuous course of conduct offenses in particular can be helpful in examining these types of questions.  This Note focuses on one particular type of continuous course of conduct offenses—“continuous sexual abuse of a child” (CSA) statutes—that has become popular in the last two decades.

Part I provides a general overview of CSA statutes and their history.  Part II briefly discusses the current constitutional doctrinal framework.  Part III focuses on California and Texas to show what their respective case law says about jury unanimity, specificity requirements for unanimity, and the continuous course of conduct exception.  Part IV provides an analysis of CSA statutes and will attempt to answer the questions of (1) whether these statutes are staying true to the purpose behind specificity in jury agreement and (2) whether these statutes may bump up against constitutional problems in the future.  Part V discusses some of the possible ways to address current CSA statutes and then provides possible solutions for how to better address the problem of prosecuting child molesters.

U-Turns on the One-Way Street: Public Rights and Representation Theory in Patent Validity Litigation

Brett Rosenthal

91 Texas L. Rev. 1227

PDF Document

In this Note, Mr. Rosenthal contends that a vigorous challenge against a patent’s validity fully vindicates the public right to access ideas in the public domain and should preclude successive challenges by future infringers.  Part I looks at the foundational tools of group litigation—joinder and consolidation—as applied in patent law, including recently adopted restrictions in the America Invents Act of 2011.  Part II asks whether the Rule 23 class action allows certification of present and future infringers for validity determinations.  Part III examines whether the “public law” nature of the validity inquiry reinvigorates the notion of “virtual representation” rejected in Taylor v. Sturgell.  Part IV analyzes whether procedural rules that facilitate the establishment of patent validity further the substantive goals of patent law and the imperatives of wise judicial administration.

Pursuing Academic Freedom After Garcetti v. Ceballos

Lauren K. Ross

91 Texas L. Rev. 1253

PDF Document

In this Note, Ms. Ross argues that the Court should recognize a constitutional, individual right to academic freedom.  The Note begins by updating and reposing William Van Alstyne’s concept of a specific theory of academic freedom, distinguishing the right to academic freedom from a more general notion of First Amendment rights.  It then turns to Garcetti v. Ceballos, providing historical context in order to understand why Garcetti marks such a change in our understanding of free speech.  The next portion of this Note considers how courts have applied Garcetti to cases raising academic freedom issues.  Using the problems revealed in the post-Garcetti decisions, this Note then suggests the Court should officially recognize a right to academic freedom and offers thoughts on what that right should encompass.

Legal Realism Untamed

Frederick Schauer

91 Texas L. Rev. 749

PDF Document

In this piece, Professor Schauer argues that law is not only about hard cases. There are easy ones as well, and understanding law requires awareness not only of litigated and then appealed disputes, but also the routine application of legal rules and doctrine.

One consequence of the existence of easy cases along with hard ones is the alleged marginalization of the skeptical challenges of Legal Realism. Legal Realism is conventionally understood, in part, to question legal doctrine’s determinacy and positive law’s causal effect on judicial decisions. But if Legal Realism’s skepticism about the constraints of positive law applies only to the sliver of legal events that are litigated cases, Legal Realism’s challenges can be kept at bay. Legal Realism may remain a valuable corrective to the view that even most appellate cases have a legally right answer, but not as a claim that undermines the routine determinacy of law.

This marginalization of Legal Realism turns out, however, to ignore a central Realist theme: the distinction between “paper rules,” on the one hand, and “real rules,” or “working rules,” on the other. The distinction between real and paper rules is well-known, but the effect of the distinction upon the supposed marginalization of Legal Realism has remained unnoticed. For when the paper rules do not describe the actual rules that judges use in making decisions, the divergence between paper and real rules will influence the distribution between easy and hard cases. Thus the distinction between paper and real rules pervades the entirety of law. The gap between paper and real rules, therefore, by producing consequences throughout law and not merely to a small subset of it, reveals the Realist challenge to be more foundational, and—importantly—less tamed.

The question Professor Schauer addresses is as fundamental as it is simple: What makes hard cases hard, and easy ones easy? The answer is empirical, varying with time, place, and area of law. But Legal Realism in its untamed version not only directs us to this question, but also suggests that the answer to the empirical question might, in some contexts and in some domains, challenge the standard view of how law works even in its routine and nonlitigated operation.

Dream On: The Obama Administration’s Nonenforcement of Immigration Laws, the DREAM Act, and the Take Care Clause

Robert J. Delahunty & John C. Yoo

91 Texas L. Rev. 781

PDF Document

In this piece, Professors Delahunty and Yoo argue that the Obama Administration’s preferred tool for domestic policy is “prosecutorial discretion” not to enforce statutes with which the President disagrees. The Obama Administration has claimed “prosecutorial discretion” most aggressively in the area of immigration. The most notable example of this trend was its June 15, 2012 decision not to enforce the removal provisions of the Immigration and Nationality Act (INA) against an estimated population of 800,000 to 1.76 million individuals illegally present in the United States. By taking this step, the Obama Administration effectively wrote into law “the DREAM Act,” whose passage had failed to that point.

In Part I, Professors Delahunty and Yoo describe the circumstances of the Administration’s June 15 nonenforcement decision and identify the central legal issues. In Part II, they examine the meaning and scope of the President’s duty to “take care” that the laws be faithfully executed. In Part III, they catalogue and review the most commonly offered and generally accepted excuses or justifications for the breach of the duty to execute the laws, such as unconstitutionality of the law, equity in individual cases, and resource limitations. The authors conclude that the June 15 decision does not fall within any of them.

Time Out of Joint

Kenneth Anderson

91 Texas L. Rev. 859

PDF Document

Anderson reviews Mary L. Dudziak’s War Time: An Idea, Its History, Its Consequences.